Law, Probability and Risk (2003) 2, 69–89
Bayesian reconstruction of traffic accidents
G ARY A. DAVIS†
Department of Civil Engineering, University of Minnesota, 122 CivE, 500 Pillsbury
Drive SE, Minneapolis, MN 55455, USA
[Received on 20 January 2003; revised on 17 April 2003; accepted on 9 May 2003]
Traffic accident reconstruction has been defined as the effort to determine, from whatever
evidence is available, how an accident happened. Traffic accident reconstruction can be
treated as a problem in uncertain reasoning about a particular event, and developments
in modeling uncertain reasoning for artificial intelligence can be applied to this problem.
Physical principles can usually be used to develop a structural model of the accident and
this model, together with an expert assessment of prior uncertainty regarding the accident’s
initial conditions, can be represented as a Bayesian network. Posterior probabilities for
the accident’s initial conditions, given evidence collected at the accident scene, can then
be computed by updating the Bayesian network. Using a possible worlds semantics,
truth conditions for counterfactual claims about the accident can be defined and used to
rigorously implement a ‘but for’ test of whether or not a speed limit violation could be
considered a cause of an accident. The logic of this approach is illustrated for a simplified
version of a vehicle/pedestrian accident, and then the approach is applied to four actual
accidents.
Keywords: possible worlds; accident reconstruction; Bayes networks; Markov chain Monte
Carlo; forensic inference.
Limited creatures that we are, we often find ourselves having to base decisions on
less than complete information. This is particularly true of many forensic problems,
and at the First International Conference on Forensic Statistics Lindley (1991) argued
that the probability calculus should be applied not only to statistical problems, but to
forensic inference more generally. Lindley focused on a class of problems for which
the hypotheses of interest were the guilt or innocence of a defendant, and the task was
to weigh the plausibility of these alternatives in the light of evidence. His proposed
solution was Bayesian, where one first determines a prior assignment of probability to the
alternative hypotheses, along with the probability of the evidence given each alternative,
and then uses Bayes’ theorem to compute posterior probabilities for the hypotheses. This
approach has since been applied to increasingly more complicated problems in forensic
identification (e.g. Balding, 2000; Dawid & Mortera, 1998), in part due to an intense
interest in interpreting DNA evidence.
† E-mail: drtrips@umn.edu
c Oxford University Press 2003, all rights reserved
70
G . A . DAVIS
1. Forensic inference and traffic accidents
Lindley also referred briefly to a different class of problems, exemplified by ‘the case of a
motorist charged with dangerous driving . . . . Here the possible criminal is known; what
is in doubt is whether there was a crime’ (1991, p. 86). Such problems are most prominent
when a traffic accident has resulted in death or serious injury, and it must be determined
if a driver should be subjected to criminal or civil penalties. The specific conditions which
define this liability vary somewhat across jurisdictions, but it is generally possible to
identify two basic issues, pertaining to the quality of driving, and to the causal relation
between the driving and the accident’s outcome. For example, in Great Britain ‘causing
death by dangerous driving’ occurs when ‘a person causes the death of another person by
driving a mechanically propelled vehicle dangerously’ while ‘dangerous driving’ is in turn
defined as driving that ‘falls far below what would be expected of a competent and careful
driver’ (Road Traffic Act, 1991). In the United States, the Uniform Vehicle Code states
that ‘homicide by vehicle’ occurs when a driver ‘is engaged in the violation of any state
law or municipal ordinance applying to the operation or use of a vehicle’ and when ‘such
violation is the proximate cause of said death’ (NCUTLO, 1992). (Italics have been added
for emphasis.)
For some accidents, eyewitness testimony may be reliable enough, and the driving
egregious enough, that questions concerning the quality of driving and its relation to
the accident are readily resolved. In other cases, however, the evidence can be entirely
circumstantial, collected by accident investigators after the event. The connections between
the evidence and the basic legal issues can then be less clear, and over the past 70 years the
practice of accident investigation and reconstruction has developed primarily to assist the
legal system in resolving such questions (Traffic Institute, 1946; Rudram & Lambourn,
1981). Baker & Fricke (1990, p. 50-3) define accident reconstruction as ‘the effort to
determine, from whatever information is available, how the accident occurred’. Typical
questions which a reconstructionist can be called on to address include ascertaining the
initial speeds and locations of the involved parties, identifying the actions taken by these
parties, and determining the degree to which avoidance actions might have been effective.
Rarely however will direct observations alone be sufficient to answer these questions, and
the reconstructionist may need to supplement the information collected at the accident’s
scene.
These issues can be illustrated by considering an instructional example used by
Greatrix (2002). On a summer afternoon in Carlisle, England, a seven year-old boy
attempted to cross a road ahead of an oncoming vehicle, and although the driver braked to a
stop, the child was struck. Measurements made at the scene yielded a skidmark 22 meters
long, with the point of collision being 12 meters from the start of the skid. It was also
noted that the speed limit on the road was 30 mph (13.4 meters/sec). A standard practice in
accident reconstruction is to use, as additional premises, variants of the kinematic formula
s = vt + (at 2 )/2
(1)
which gives the distance s travelled during time interval t by an object with initial velocity
v while undergoing a constant acceleration of a. In this case, test skids conducted after the
accident suggested that a braking deceleration a = −7·24 meters/sec2 was plausible, and
this value together with the measured skidmark of 22 meters gives the speed of the vehicle
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
71
at the start of the skid as 17·8 meters/sec. Citing statistical evidence on the distribution
of driver reaction times (denoted here by t p ), Greatrix used a representative value of
1·33 seconds to deduce that the vehicle was 35·7 meters from the collision point when
the driver noticed the pedestrian. If the vehicle has been travelling instead at the posted
speed of 30 mph (13·4 meters/sec), the driver would have needed only 30·2 meters to stop
and so, other things being equal, would not have hit the child. Thus the evidence could be
taken as supporting claims that the driver was speeding, and that had the driver not been
speeding, the accident would not have happened. At this point though a different expert
could argue that no one knows for certain either the actual braking deceleration or the
driver’s actual reaction time. The alternative values of a = −5·5 meters/sec2 and t p = 1·0
s imply that the magnitude of the speed limit violation was only about 5 mph, and that the
vehicle would not have stopped before reaching the collision point, even if the initial speed
had been 30 mph. It could then be claimed that both the degree to which the driver’s speed
violated the speed limit, and the causal connection between that violation and the result,
are open to doubt.
One way to view this example is as an attempt to answer three types of questions. The
first type, which can be called factual questions, concerns the actual conditions associated
with this particular accident. These include the paths of the pedestrian and vehicle, the
initial speed of the vehicle, and the relation between this speed and the posted speed limit.
Answering this type of question is what Baker and Fricke consider the role of accident
reconstruction proper. The second type, which can be called counterfactual questions,
starts with a stipulation of the facts, but then goes beyond these and attempts to determine
what would have happened had certain specific conditions been different. In the example,
determining whether or not the vehicle would have stopped before reaching the pedestrian,
had the initial speed been equal to the posted limit, is a question of this type. Counterfactual
questions usually arise in accident reconstruction when attempting to identify what Baker
called ‘causal factors’, which are circumstances ‘contributing to a result without which the
result could not have occurred’ (Baker, 1975, p. 274). Posing and answering counterfactual
questions has been referred to as ‘avoidance analysis’ (Limpert, 1989), or ‘sequence of
events analysis’ (Hicks, 1989) in the accident reconstruction literature. Finally, the third
type of question arises because of uncertainty regarding the conditions of the accident,
which leads to uncertainty concerning the answers to the first two types of question.
How best to account for uncertainty in an accident reconstruction is currently an
unresolved issue. A common recommendation has been to perform sensitivity analyses,
in which the values of selected input variables are changed and estimates recomputed
(Schockenhoff et al., 1985; Hicks, 1989; Niederer, 1991). When the conclusions of the
reconstruction (e.g. that the driver was speeding) are insensitive to this variation they
can be regarded as well-supported, but if different yet plausible combinations of input
values produce differing results, this approach is inconclusive. This limitation has been
recognized, and has motivated several authors to apply probabilistic methods. Brach (1994)
has illustrated how the method of statistical differentials can be used to compute the
variance of an estimate, given a differentiable expression for the desired estimate and a
specification of the means and variances of distributions characterizing the uncertainty
in the expression’s arguments. Kost & Werner (1994) and Wood & O’Riordain (1994)
have suggested that Monte Carlo simulation can be used for more complicated models
where tractable solutions are not at hand. The Monte Carlo methods also produce
72
G . A . DAVIS
approximate probability distributions characterizing the uncertainty of estimates, rather
than just means and variances. Particularly interesting are the examples used by Wood and
O’Riordain, where simulated outcomes inconsistent with measurements were rejected, in
effect producing posterior conditional distributions for the quantities of interest. These
posterior distributions were then used to compute the probability of a counterfactual claim,
that the accident would not have occurred had a vehicle’s initial speed been different.
More recently, Rose et al. (2001) have employed a Monte Carlo approach similar to
that of Wood and O’Riordain. A weakness of this approach, rooted in the appearance
of the Borel paradox when making inferences using deterministic simulation models,
has been identified by Hoogstrate & Spek (2002), who used Bayesian melding (Poole
& Raftery, 2000) to get around this problem. Roughly concomitant with the developing
interest in probabilistic accident reconstruction has been an interest in using Bayesian
networks to support more traditional forensic inference (Edwards, 1991; Aitken et al.,
1996; Dawid & Evett, 1997; Curran et al., 1998). Bayesian networks can be used to
represent an expert’s knowledge concerning some class of systems, together with his or
her uncertainty concerning the state of a particular system in that class. The system’s
state is characterized by the values taken on by a set of variables, and the dependences
among the system variables are described by specifying a set of deterministic and/or
stochastic relationships (Jensen, 1996). Davis (1999, 2001) has illustrated how Bayesian
network methods and Markov chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) computational techniques can
be combined to accomplish a Bayesian reconstruction of vehicle/pedestrian accidents.
Despite this growing interest in using probabilistic reasoning in accident reconstruction, there appears to be some confusion about the relation between these applications and
traditional statistical reasoning. Brach faulted sensitivity analyses because ‘the statistical
nature of the variations is not explicitly taken into account’, (1994, p. 148), while Wood and
O’Riordain referred to an expression giving the coefficient of variation for an individual
speed estimate as ‘ . . . a statistical approach’, (1994, p. 130). Rose et al. recommended
Monte Carlo simulation because it produces ‘statistically relevant conclusions regarding
the probable ∆V experienced by a vehicle’ (2001, p. 2). These quotations suggest a
tendency to view probabilistic accident reconstruction as an exercise in statistical inference.
Lindley (1991), and more recently Schum (2000), have argued though that statistical
inference problems are only a subset of the forensic problems to which probabilistic
methods can be applied. Although reasonable people can disagree on how to define
the discipline of statistics, statistical problems typically involve making inferences about
how some characteristic is distributed over a population of entities, using measurements
made on a sample from that population. Probabilities are used to express uncertainty
about parameters characterizing the population distribution, and this uncertainty can in
principle be reduced by increasing the sample’s size. In contrast, the usual objective of an
accident reconstruction is to make inferences about an individual event, and probabilities
are assigned to statements about that event. When an individual accident can be regarded as
exchangeable with the members of a reference population, pre-established characteristics
of that population could be used to make these probability assignments, but once the
characteristics of the reference distribution are known, information about additional
accidents in the reference population reveals nothing more about the accident at hand.
The confusion concerning the appropriate role of probability in accident reconstruction
can at least in part be attributed to two fundamentally different meanings attached to
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
73
probability statements, on the one hand referring to expected relative frequencies in
repeated trials of ‘chance setups’, Hacking (1965) and on the other referring to a degree
of credibility assigned to propositions. This duality was apparently present in the initial
development of probability theory in the seventeenth century (Hacking, 1975), recurs
in philosophical treatments of probability (e.g. Carnap, 1945; Lewis, 1980), and has
reappeared in the study of logics for artificial reasoning (Halpern, 1990). The view we shall
adopt here is that an accident reconstruction produces expert opinion about a particular,
past event. To quote Baker and Fricke: ‘Opinions or conclusions are the products of
accident reconstruction. To the extent that reports of direct observations are available and
can be depended on as facts, reconstruction is unnecessary’ (1990, p. 50-4). Statements of
opinion can be more or less certain however, depending on the certainty attached to their
premises. If this uncertainty is graded using probabilities, then the probability calculus
can be used as a logic to derive the uncertainty attached to conclusions. This approach is
what Howson (1993) calls ‘personalistic Bayesianism’ but before continuing it should be
noted that it is by no means the only alternative available. Debate continues as to when
or even if the probability calculus is the appropriate logic for uncertain reasoning, and the
issue shows no signs of being resolved anytime in the near future. The development of
logics to capture aspects of reasoning under uncertainty is an active area of research, and
an overview of some of this work can be found in Dubois & Prade (1993). Summaries of
the arguments for and against the Bayesian approach can be found in Howson (1993) and
Earman (1992).
2. Accidents, probability, and possible worlds
This use of probability can be brought into sharper focus by considering a simpler model
of a vehicle/pedestrian collision, having just three Boolean variables. Variable v denotes
the vehicle’s initial speed, and takes on the value 0 if the vehicle was not speeding and the
value 1 if it was. Variable x denotes the vehicle’s initial distance, and takes on the value 0
if this distance was ‘short’ and 1 if it was ‘long’ (the problem of determining exactly what
is meant by ‘short’ and ‘long’ will, for the time being, be ignored). Variable y denotes
whether or not a collision takes place, with 0 being no collision and 1 being collision. y is
assumed to be related to v and x via the structural equation
y = (1 − x) + x ∗ v
(2)
where + and ∗ denote Boolean addition and multiplication, respectively. In words, a
collision occurs if either the initial distance is short (1 − x = 1), or if the initial distance is
long but the vehicle is speeding (x ∗ v = 1). Since all variables are Boolean, the relationship
between y, x and v can be tabulated as in Table 1.
In Table 1 each assignment of values to v and x determines a possible way the
vehicle/pedestrian encounter could have occurred. The rows of such tables have been
variously referred to as ‘states of affairs’, ‘scenarios’ or ‘system states’, but a longrunning practice in philosophical logic (e.g. Lewis, 1976), which is becoming increasingly
common in research on artificial intelligence (e.g. Bacchus, 1990; Halpern, 1990), is to
follow Leibniz, and call them ‘possible worlds’. Uncertainty can then arise in an accident
reconstruction when the available evidence is not sufficient to determine which possible
74
G . A . DAVIS
TABLE 1 Possible worlds and
a probability distribution for the
simple Boolean collision model
World
1
2
3
4
v
0
1
0
1
x
0
0
1
1
y
1
1
0
1
yv=0
1
1
0
0
P
1/4
1/4
1/4
1/4
world was the actual one. For example, suppose one is interested in whether or not the
vehicle was speeding, but the only evidence is that the accident occurred (y = 1). Table 1
shows that the condition y = 1 eliminates world 3 as a possibility, but of the remaining
three worlds at least one has v = 0 and one has v = 1, so the best that can be said is that it is
possible, but not necessary, that the vehicle was speeding. On the other hand, suppose that
a reliable witness reported that the initial distance was ‘long’ (x = 1) when the pedestrian
entered the road. Only world 4 has x = 1 and y = 1, and in this world v = 1, so here the
evidence implies that the vehicle was speeding.
In any given possible world a statement is either true or false, so uncertainty about
a statement arises when a set of possible worlds contains some members where that
statement is true, and other members where it is false. Uncertainty can be modelled by
placing a probability distribution on the set of possible worlds, so that the probability
attached to a statement is simply the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds
where that statement is true. For example, suppose that each of the possible worlds in
Table 1 is regarded as a priori equally probable, so that each has a prior probability of 1/4.
One then observes that a collision has occurred. The conditional probability of speeding
given that the collision occurred is then
P[v = 1|y = 1] = P[v = 1 and y = 1]/P[y = 1] = (1/4 + 1/4)/(1/4 + 1/4 + 1/4) = 2/3.
(3)
This possible worlds approach can also be used to specify truth conditions for
counterfactual statements, such as ‘if the vehicle had not been speeding, the collision would
not have occurred’, by considering what is the case in the ‘closest’ possible world where
the antecedent is true. That is, a counterfactual conditional is said to be true in this (the
actual) world, if its consequent is true in the closest possible world where the antecedent
is true. For instance, suppose the actual world is world 4 (v = 1, x = 1) and world 3
(v = 0, x = 1) is taken to be the world closest to world 4, but having v = 0. Letting
yv=0 = 0 stand for the counterfactual claim that had v been 0, y would have been 0, Table
1 shows that since y = 0 is true in the possible world 3, yv=0 = 0 should be taken as
true in the actual world 4. On the other hand, yv=0 = 0 should not be taken as true in
world 2 (v = 1, x = 0) if world 1 (v = 0, x = 0) is taken as the closest with v = 0. As
with indicative statements, probabilities of counterfactual statements can be determined
by computing the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds where that statement
is true. For example, again treating the possible worlds as a priori equally probable, the
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
75
probability that speeding was a necessary cause of the collision can be evaluated as
P[yv=0 = 0|y = 1] = P[yv=0 = 0 and y = 1]/P[y = 1] = 1/3.
(4)
This simple example illustrates both a deterministic and a probabilistic approach
to accident reconstruction, and these two approaches have a similar structure. The
deterministic reconstruction started with a statement describing an observation (y = 1)
and then added a structural premise stating the assumed causal relation between this
outcome and the variables describing the initial conditions. Boolean algebra, supplemented
with a possible worlds semantics for counterfactual conditionals, was then used to derive
statements about the initial conditions, and about the causal connection between the initial
conditions and the outcome. Ideally, the premises of a reconstruction argument should be
strong enough to logically imply definite conclusions about the accident, but as often as
not the appearance of deductive certitude is achieved by adding premises whose certainty
is questionable. The probabilistic reconstruction also began with the observation and the
structural premises, but then supplemented these with a probabilistic premise, in this case
a prior probability distribution over the possible worlds. It was then possible to use the
probability calculus to derive probabilistic conclusions about the accident’s provenance.
These ideas are not new. The distinction between probabilities as relative frequencies
for actual world populations, and probabilities as measures on models of interpreted formal
languages (what we are calling possible worlds) can be found in Carnap (1971) while
Lewis (1973) and Stalnaker (1968) have developed the idea that the truth conditions
for a counterfactual conditional are given by what is true in closest possible worlds.
Lewis (1976) illustrates how these notions can be combined to define probabilities of
counterfactual conditionals, and Balke & Pearl (1994) have shown how this approach
can be applied to a wide class of inference problems using Bayesian network methods.
Chapters 7–9 of Pearl (2000) describe a more detailed development of Balke and Pearl’s
approach, based on what Pearl calls ‘causal models’. To specify a causal model, one first
identifies a set of background variables and a set of endogenous variables, and then for each
endogenous variable specifies a structural equation describing how that variable changes
in response to changes in the background or other endogenous variables. A possible world
is then determined by an assignment of values to the model’s background variables. In
Greatrix’s example, the vehicle’s initial distance (x), its speed (v), the braking deceleration
(a) and the driver’s reaction time (t p ) can be taken as background variables, while the
length of the skidmark (s) and a collision indicator (y) are endogenous. The structural
equation for the skidmark would then be
s(v, a) = −v 2 /(2a),
while the structural equation of the collision indicator would be
1, if x < vt p − v 2 /2a
y(x, t p , v, a) =
0, otherwise.
(5)
(6)
Structural models are especially useful in assessing the plausibility of causal claims
because they allow one to give an unambiguous definition of truth conditions for a class of
causal statements, along the lines of the closest possible world approach outlined above.
76
G . A . DAVIS
For example, suppose that in the actual world v = 18 meters/sec , a = −7 meters/sec2 ,
x = 40 meters, and t p = 1·5 seconds. Then in the actual world x = 40 meters while
vt p − v 2 /2a = 50·1 meters, so by (6) y = 1 and the collision occurs. Previously, the
causal effect of speeding was informally defined as whether or not, other things equal,
the collision would not have occurred if the vehicle had not been speeding. This ‘other
things equal’ condition can be made explicit by defining the closest possible world as
the one where all background variables have the same value except for v, which is set to
v = 13·4 meters/sec . In this world x = 40 meters, while vt p − v 2 /2a = 32·9 meters,
implying y = 0. So in the actual world, yv=13·4 = 0 is true, and speeding could be
considered a causal factor for the collision.
In the Greatrix example, a deterministic assessment of whether or not obeying the speed
limit would have prevented a pedestrian accident consisted of three steps:
(a) estimating the vehicle’s initial speed and location, using the measured skid marks
and nominal values for a and t p ,
(b) setting the vehicle’s initial speed to the counterfactual value,
(c) using the same values of a and t p along with the counterfactual speed to predict if
the vehicle would then have stopped before hitting the pedestrian.
Each assignment of values to the background variables corresponds to a possible world,
and placing a prior probability distribution over the possible worlds produces what Pearl
calls a probabilistic causal model. As before, the probability assigned to a statement about
the accident is determined by the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds in which
that statement is true. This applies both to factual statements, such as ‘the vehicle was
speeding’, and to counterfactual statements, such as ‘if the vehicle had not been speeding,
the collision would not have occurred’. Steps (a)–(c) correspond, in probabilistic causal
models, to what Pearl calls abduction, action and prediction. For the problem of assessing
the probability that yv=v∗ = 0, given a measured skidmark s, these would involve
(A) Abduction: compute P[x, t p , v, a|s];
(B) Action: set v = v ∗ ;
(C) Prediction: compute P[yv=v∗ = 0|s].
In our simple Boolean example, where the number of possible worlds was finite and
small, the abduction step could be carried out by a simple application of the definition
of conditional probability, while the prediction step simply required summing the
posterior probabilities over possible worlds. For more complicated models, however,
this direct approach is not computationally feasible, but Balke & Pearl (1994) have
shown that for models which can be represented as Bayesian networks, steps (A)–(C)
can be carried out by applying Bayesian updating to an appropriately constructed ‘twin
network’, where the original Bayesian network has been augmented with additional nodes
representing the closest possible world. In accident reconstruction the structural equations
will often be nonlinear and involve several arguments, while many of the underlying
variables will be represented as continuous quantities. This means that the exact updating
methods developed for discrete or normal/linear Bayesian networks (Jensen, 1996) can
be applied only after constructing a discrete approximation of the reconstruction model.
Alternatively, Monte Carlo computational methods could be used to compute approximate
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
77
x
s2
d
vt p
xs
s1
F IG . 1. Major variables appearing in the vehicle/pedestrian collision model.
but asymptotically exact updates for the original reconstruction model, and this latter
approach is used in what follows.
3. Bayesian reconstruction of actual accidents
These ideas will be applied to four actual accidents, three involving a vehicle and
a pedestrian, and one involving two vehicles at an intersection. The first of the
vehicle/pedestrian accidents is Greatrix’s example described above, while the other two
are taken from a group of fatal accidents investigated by the University of Adelaide’s Road
Accident Research Unit (RARU) (McLean et al., 1994). The scenario for the pedestrian
accidents runs as follows. The driver of a vehicle travelling at a speed of v notices an
impending collision with a pedestrian, travelling at a speed v2 , when the front of the vehicle
is a distance x from the potential point of impact. After a perception/reaction time of t p
the driver locks the brakes, and the vehicle decelerates at a constant rate − f g, where g
denotes gravitational acceleration and f is the braking ‘drag factor’ which, following a
standard practice in accident reconstruction, expresses the deceleration as a multiple of
g. After a transient time ts the tyres begin making skid marks, and the vehicle comes to a
stop, leaving a skidmark of length s1 . Before stopping, the vehicle strikes the pedestrian at a
speed of vi , and the pedestrian is thrown into the air and comes to rest a distance d from the
point of impact. In addition, if the pedestrian was struck after the vehicle began skidding,
it may be possible to measure a distance s2 running from the point of impact to the end
of the skidmark. Figure 1 illustrates the collision scenario (with xs denoting the distance
travelled during the braking transient.) The abduction step of Pearl’s three-step method
involves computing the posterior distributions of the model’s unobserved variables, given
some subset of the measurements d, s1 , s2 . Figure 2 represents the collision model as a
directed acyclic graph summarizing the conditional dependence structure, and including
nodes to represent the counterfactual speed v ∗ and the counterfactual collision indicator
y ∗ . To complete the model it is necessary to specify deterministic or stochastic relations
for the arrows appearing in Figure 2, and prior distributions for the background variables
x, v, t p , ts , v2 , and f .
The structural equations for this model have been described elsewhere (Davis, 2001;
Davis et al., 2002), and so the details will not be repeated. Roughly, the relationship
between the expected skidmark lengths and the background variables is governed by
78
G . A . DAVIS
v*
y*
v2
xx
s1s1
t pt
d
p
t st
s
vi
vi
ff
v
s2
s2
F IG . 2. Directed acyclic graph representation of vehicle/pedestrian collision model.
the kinematic equation (1), while the measured skidmark is the result of combining
random measurement error with the expected length. The coefficient of variation for
this measurement error was taken to be 10% (Garrott & Guenther, 1982). An empirical
relationship between impact speed and throw distance was determined by fitting a model
to the results of 55 crash tests between cars and pedestrian dummies, and is described in
Davis et al. (2002). Finally, the counterfactual collision variable y ∗ was taken to be zero
(i.e. the collision was avoided) if either the vehicle stopped before reaching the collision
point, of if the pedestrian managed to travel an additional 3·0 meters before the vehicle
arrived at the collision point.
Selection of the prior probability distributions for the background variables was less
straightforward. As indicated earlier, these distributions should be interpreted as expert
opinions concerning plausible ranges of values, although statistical information might, in
some cases, be used to inform these opinions. The strategy used for these examples was
to identify priors that appeared on their face to be consistent with current reconstruction
practice. In deterministic sensitivity analyses it is often possible to identify defensible prior
ranges for background variables (Niederer, 1991), and Wood & O’Riordain (1994, p. 137)
argue that, in the absence of more specific information, uniform distributions restricted
to these ranges offer a plausible extension of the deterministic sensitivity methods.
Following these suggestions, the reconstructions described in this paper used uniform prior
distributions. Specifically, the range for f was [0·55, 0·9], and was taken from Fricke
(1990, p. 62), where 0·55 corresponds to the lower bound for a dry, travelled asphalt
pavement and 0·9 is what Fricke considers a reasonable upper bound for most cases. The
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
79
TABLE 2 Features of three reconstructed pedestrian accidents: distances
are in meters, speeds in meters/second
Case
Greatrix
RARU 89-H002
RARU 91-H025
Scene data
s1
s2
22
10
23·5 8·1
14·9 4·5
d
14·8
-
Pedestrian characteristics
Running speed
Sex Age
Lower
Upper
M
7
1·8
5·1
M
5
2·5
4·5
F
9
3·3
5·6
range for the perception/reaction time, t p , was [0·5 seconds, 2·5 seconds], which brackets
the values obtained by Fambro et al. (1998) in surprise braking tests, and the midpoint of
which (1.5 seconds) equals a popular default value (Stewart-Morris, 1995). For the braking
transient time, Neptune et al. (1995) reported values ranging between 0·1 and 0·35 seconds
for a well-tuned braking system, while Reed & Keskin (1989) reported values in the range
of 0·4–0·5 seconds, so the chosen range was [0·1 seconds, 0·5 seconds]. The bounds for
the pedestrian speeds (v2 ) were different for the three cases, varying according to the age
and sex of the pedestrian, and were selected to include the 15th and 85th percentile figures
for children’s running speeds tabulated in Eubanks & Hill (1998, pp. 82–86). The ranges
for the initial distance and initial speed were chosen to be wide enough that no reasonable
possibility would be excluded a priori. The range for v was [5 meters/sec, 50 meters/sec],
but initial attempts to apply MCMC methods revealed convergence problems when the
initial distance was selected as a background variable. To remedy this the model was
re-parameterized with the distance from the collision point to the start of braking as a
background variable, and the prior for this initial braking distance was taken to be uniform
with range [0 meters, 200 meters]. Note that the initial distance is then simply the sum of
this initial braking distance and the distance travelled during the perception/reaction time.
Table 2 displays information for each of the three vehicle/pedestrian accidents, including
the age and sex of the pedestrian, the lower and upper bounds for the pedestrian’s running
speed used in the reconstruction, and the skidmark and throw distance measurements. The
computer program WinBUGS (Spiegelhalter et al., 2000) was used to generate Monte
Carlo samples of the quantities of interest. (Copies of the WinBUGS code for these
examples are available from the author on request.) In each case a 5000 iteration burn-in
was followed by 150 000 iterations, with the outcome of every 10th iteration being saved
for the MCMC sample. Inspection of traces and autocorrelations indicated no obvious
problems with nonstationarity or failure to converge.
As noted earlier, determining liability involves addressing (at least) two basic issues,
one concerning the actual driving, and one concerning the causal connection between that
driving and the occurrence of the accident. With regard to the first issue, often an important
concern is the speeds of the vehicles involved, and the relation of those speeds to any speed
limits. With regard to the second issue, an important question is often whether or not an
initial speed equal to the legal limit would, other things equal, have been sufficient to
prevent the accident. Figures 3–5 display, for each of the three pedestrian accidents, a plot
of the posterior probability density for the speed of the involved vehicle and a plot of the
80
G . A . DAVIS
1.1
1
Probabilities
0.8
p1i
0.6
pdr i
0.4
0.2
0
0
15
20
25
18.645
30
35
40
speed mphi
Speed (mph)
45
50
55
60
59.043
P[v | y=1&e]
PA(v)
F IG . 3. Posterior density for vehicle’s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed:
Greatrix’s example.
probability the accident would have been avoided, as a function of the counterfactual initial
speed.
Figure 3, which shows results for Greatrix’s example, indicates that the posterior
distribution of the vehicle’s initial speed is centred at about 45 mph (72 km/h), and that
a probable range for the initial speed is between 35 mph (56 km/h) and 55 mph (88 km/h).
The posterior probability that the vehicle was travelling at or below the posted speed limit
of 30 mph (48 km/h) is essentially zero. Figure 3 also indicates that had the initial speed
been at or below the posted speed limit it is very probable that either the driver would have
been able to stop before hitting the pedestrian, or the pedestrian would have been able to
clear the vehicle’s path before collision. So even after allowing for reasonable uncertainty
in the vehicle’s braking deceleration, in the driver’s reaction time and for a fairly substantial
measurement error in measuring the skidmarks, it appears highly probable that the driver
was speeding, and that speeding was a causal factor in this accident.
Figure 4 shows results for the RARU’s case 89-H002, in which a 5 year-old boy ran into
a road from behind a parked car, stopped briefly in the middle of the road, and was struck
when he attempted to run across the far lane. The speed limit on this road was 60 km/h. In
this case the posterior probability of the vehicle’s initial speed is centred at about 73 km/h,
with a probable range being between 60 km/h and 90 km/h. The posterior probability that
the initial speed was greater than 60 km/h was about 0·985, and the probability the collision
would have been avoided had the initial speed been equal to 60 km/h was equal to about
0·84. Although less obvious than in the Greatrix example, again it appears that the vehicle
81
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
1.1
1
Probabilities
0.8
p 1i
0.6
p dri
0.4
0.2
0
0
30
40
50
30
60
70
80
90
speed km/hi
Speed (km/h)
100
95
P[v | y=1&e]
PA(v)
F IG . 4. Posterior density for vehicle’s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed:
RARU case 89-H002.
1.1
1
Probabilities
0.8
p1i
0.6
pdr i
0.4
0.2
0
0
30
40
30
50
60
70
speed km/hi
Speed (km/h)
80
90
100
95
P[v | y=1&e]
PA (v)
F IG . 5. Posterior density for vehicle’s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed:
RARU case 91-H025.
82
G . A . DAVIS
was probably speeding, and that speeding was probably a causal factor in this accident.
Figure 5 shows similar results for the RARU’s case 91-H025. For this case the posterior
probability that the driver was exceeding the 60 km/h speed limit is only about 0·5, and
the probability the accident would have been prevented had the initial speed been 60 km/h
is only about 0·27. Unlike the first two cases, here it appears difficult to maintain that the
driver should be held liable.
The fourth illustrative accident involved a collision between two vehicles at a twoway stop-controlled intersection in the United States, and is described in Fricke (1990,
p. 68). In this accident vehicle #1 attempted to turn left onto a state highway from a stopcontrolled approach, and was struck broadside by vehicle #2, which was westbound on
the highway. Vehicle #2 left a skidmark of about 73 feet (22·3 meters) prior to impact,
and after impact the two vehicles slid together in a northwesterly direction, across the
concrete surface of the intersection and onto a grassy shoulder, before coming to a stop.
Test skids indicated that drag factors of 0·75 and 0·45 were plausible for the concrete
and grass surfaces, respectively. Because the two vehicles followed a common direction
after the impact, a ‘forward’ reconstruction, in which the conservation-of-momentum
equations are used to predict the after-impact speeds and directions was not feasible,
so a ‘backward’ approach, where one estimates speeds working back from the point of
rest, was used instead. WinBUGS was used to compute Monte Carlo estimates of the
posterior distributions for the background variables, including the initial speed of vehicle
#2, as well as estimates of the probability the collision would have been avoided as a
function of different counterfactual initial speeds. The WinBUGS code used to generate
these estimates has been listed in the Appendix. The collision was treated as having
been avoided if either vehicle #2 managed to stop before reaching the point of collision
or if vehicle #1 managed to travel an additional 20 feet (6·1 meters) before vehicle #2
arrived at the collision point. Because the objective for this example was to see if Bayesian
reconstruction could produce results similar to Fricke’s deterministic approach, relatively
narrow uncertainty ranges were used. Skidmark measurement error was assumed to be
normal with a standard deviation of five feet (1·5 meters), the uncertainty for measured
angles was taken to be ±2·5◦ around Fricke’s values, and the uncertainties in the drag
factors were taken to be ±0·05.
Figure 6 shows the posterior probability density for vehicle #2’s initial speed and the
probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed. Inspection of this figure reveals
that the initial speed of vehicle #2 was most probably around 92 mph (148 km/h), and the
bounds of a 95% credible interval for this speed were 86 mph (141 km/h) and 99 mph
(162 km/h). Also, for initial speeds below about 60 mph (97 km/h) it is almost certain,
other things equal, that this accident would have been avoided. Taking the posted speed
limit on the state highway as 55 mph (88·5 km/h), it can be concluded that vehicle #2
was quite probably speeding, and that speeding was quite probably a causal factor for this
accident.
4. Conclusion
Arguments can be usefully classified as deductive or inductive, deductive arguments
being those where the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion, while
inductive arguments are those where the premises only make the conclusion more or less
83
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
1.1
1
Probabilities
0.8
p 1i
0.6
p dr i
0.4
0.2
0
0
40
60
50
80
100
speed mph i
Speed (mph)
120
140
140
P[v | y=1&e]
PA(v)
F IG . 6. Posterior density for vehicle’s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed:
vehicle 2 in Fricke 1990 two-vehicle example.
probable. Although deductive certainty is the standard expected in mathematics, in forensic
inference nontrivial examples of deductive certainty are rare (Evett, 1996). Investigation
and reconstruction of traffic accidents is often done to support criminal and civil legal
proceedings, the objective being to use the evidence from an accident to identify or exclude
possible causal factors, as rationally and objectively as is possible. It is often possible
to identify an underlying causal structure for a reconstruction problem, but deductive
certainty is not possible because the initial conditions of the accident cannot be measured,
and are usually underdetermined by the available evidence. To a greater or lesser extent
then, the reconstructionist must supplement the evidence with prior knowledge concerning
the values taken on by unmeasured variables, and uncertainty in this prior knowledge
induces uncertainty in the estimates and conclusions. At present there is no comprehensive
or commonly accepted method for rationally accounting for this uncertainty but if, as
Lindley (1991) argues, the probability calculus is an appropriate logic for reasoning
about uncertainty, then an accident reconstruction problem can often be formulated as
an example of processing information in a Bayesian network. The causal nature of the
relations in a reconstruction model also means that results developed by Pearl and his
associates can be used to rigorously pose and answer selected counterfactual questions
about an accident. Because reconstruction models often contain continuous variables and
deterministic relationships, the exact updating methods developed for finite Bayesian
networks are not at present well-suited to accident reconstruction, but approximations
using Monte Carlo methods are more promising.
The focus of this paper has been on determining whether or not speeding should be
84
G . A . DAVIS
considered a causal factor in road accidents. Causal factors are analogous to what Pearl
(2000) calls necessary causes, since their absence is sufficient to prevent the accident.
Road accidents usually result though from a particular combination of several causal
factors, none of which was sufficient in and of itself to produce the accident. An intriguing
extension of this Bayesian approach would be toward identifying what Baker calls the
cause of an accident, that is, the complete set of causal factors which, if reproduced, would
result in an identical accident (1975, p. 284). This however is a topic for future research.
It is worth restating that probabilistic accident reconstruction should be viewed as
uncertain reasoning about a particular, individual event, not as statistical reasoning about
the aggregate properties of a population. The importance of this distinction is brought
out clearly in recent attempts to construct artificial systems exemplifying these types of
reasoning, where a semantics for statistical propositions can be defined for a population
of entities existing in a single world, while a semantics for uncertain propositions about
individual entities appears to require quantification, and hence probabilities, defined on
a set of possible worlds (Halpern, 1990). Prior statements of probability concerning the
conditions of an accident should then be interpreted as expressing an expert’s degrees
of belief concerning possible ways the accident might have transpired, while posterior
statements of probability express how those degrees of belief should be modified in the
light of evidence (or supposition). This view is consistent with recent thinking in other
areas of forensic inference (Taroni et al., 2001).
Finally, probabilistic accident reconstruction can also be viewed as an example of
eliminative induction, where one begins with a set of possible hypotheses, and the effect
of evidence is to raise the probabilities of some of these, while reducing the probability
of others (Earman, 1992, chapter 7). Ideally, the available evidence should be sufficient to
deductively entail one hypothesis to the exclusion of the others, as in an Agatha Christie
story or the game of Clue. In practice this is rarely the case, and decisions must usually be
made when the best that can be said is that the actual case is contained in some more or
less probable set of possible cases. This suggests that the two problem types mentioned in
Lindley (1991) are not as dissimilar as might have been thought. In both Bayesian accident
reconstruction and in the Bayesian approach to forensic identification (e.g. Balding, 2000)
one begins with a set of possibilities and a prior probability distribution over this set. In
the former case the possibilities are assignments of values to background variables, while
in the latter case they are possible suspects. In both cases one then uses Bayes’ theorem to
compute posterior probabilities assigned to subsets of these possibilities, with the hope that
a clear decision will emerge. Lindley (1991) also argues that when the appropriate legal
decision is not clear, it should be determined as that which maximizes expected utility.
How this idea might be applied to traffic accident cases is an interesting subject, but one
that is beyond the scope of this paper.
Acknowledgement
This research was supported by the Intelligent Transportation Systems Institute at the
University of Minnesota.
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
85
R EFERENCES
A ITKEN , C., C ONNOLLY, T., G AMMERMAN , A., Z HANG , G., BAILEY, D., G ORDON , R. &
O LDFIELD , R. 1996 Statistical modeling in specific case analysis. Science and Justice, 36,
245–255.
BACCHUS , F. 1990 Representing and Reasoning with Probabilistic Knowledge. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
BAKER , J. 1975 Traffic Accident Investigation Manual. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Traffic Institute.
BAKER , J. & F RICKE , L. 1990 Process of traffic accident reconstruction. Traffic Accident
Reconstruction. (L. Fricke, ed.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Traffic Institute.
BALDING , D. 2000 Interpreting DNA evidence: Can probability theory help? Statistical Science in
the Courtroom. (J. Gastwirth, ed.). New York: Springer, pp. 51–70.
BALKE , A. & P EARL , J. 1994 Probabilistic evaluation of counterfactual queries. Proceedings of
12th National Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Menlo Park, NJ: AAAI Press, pp. 230–237.
B RACH , R. 1994 Uncertainty in accident reconstruction calculation. Accident Reconstruction:
Technology and Animation IV. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc., pp. 147–153.
C ARNAP , R. 1945 The two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5,
513–532.
C ARNAP , R. 1971 A basic system of inductive logic, part I. Studies in Inductive Logic and
Probability, Vol. I. (R. Carnap & R. Jeffrey, eds). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press,
pp. 33–166.
C URRAN , J., T RIGGS , C., B UCKLETON , J., WALSH , K. & H ICKS , T. 1998 Assessing transfer
probabilities in a Bayesian interpretation of forensic glass evidence. Science and Justice, 38,
15–21.
DAVIS , G. 1999 Using graphical Markov models and Gibbs sampling to reconstruct vehicle/pedestrian accidents. Proceedings of the Conference Traffic Safety on Two Continents.
Linkoping, Sweden: Swedish National Road and Transport Research Institute.
DAVIS , G. 2001 Using Bayesian networks to identify the causal effect of speeding in individual
vehicle/pedestrian collisions. Proceedings of the 17th Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial
Intelligence. (J. Breese & D. Koller, eds). San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann, pp. 105–111.
DAVIS , G., S ANDERSON , K. & DAVULURI , S. 2002 Development and Testing of a Vehicle/Pedestrian Collision Model for Neighborhood Traffic Control, Report 2002-23. St. Paul,
MN: Minnesota Department of Transportation.
DAWID , A. & E VETT , I. 1997 Using a graphical method to assist the evaluation of complicated
patterns of evidence. Journal of Forensic Science, 42, 226–231.
DAWID , P. & M ORTERA , J. 1998 Forensic identification with imperfect evidence. Biometrika, 85,
835–849.
D UBOIS , D. & P RADE , H. 1993 A glance at non-standard models and logics of uncertainty and
vagueness. Philosophy of Probability. (J.-P. Dubucs, ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 169–222.
E ARMAN , J. 1992 Bayes or Bust?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
E DWARDS , W. 1991 Influence diagrams, Bayesian imperialism, and the Collins case: An appeal to
reason. Cardozo Law Review, 13, 1025–1079.
E UBANKS , J. & H ILL , P. 1998 Pedestrian Accident Reconstruction and Litigation. Tuscon, AZ:
Lawyers and Judges Publishing Co.
E VETT , I. 1996 Expert evidence and forensic misconceptions of the nature of exact science. Science
and Justice, 36, 118–122.
FAMBRO , D., KOPPA , R., P ICHA , D. & F ITZPATRICK , K. 1998 Driver perception-brake response
86
G . A . DAVIS
in stopping sight distance situations. Paper 981410 presented at 78th Annual Meeting of
Transportation Research Board Washington, DC.
F RICKE , L. 1990 Traffic Accident Reconstruction. Evanston, IL: Traffic Institute, Northwestern
University.
G ARROTT , W. & G UENTHER , D. 1982 Determination of precrash parameters from skid mark
analysis. Transportation Research Record, 893, 38–46.
G REATRIX , G. 2002 AI lecture notes 2: Analysis of a simple accident. Accident Investigation Lecture Notes, World Wide Website http://scratchy.spods.co.uk/~greatrix/AINotes.
html, December 27, 2002.
H ACKING , I. 1965 The Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
H ACKING , I. 1975 The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
H ALPERN , J. 1990 An analysis of first-order logics of probability. Artificial Intelligence, 46, 311–
350.
H ICKS , J. 1989 Traffic accident reconstruction. Forensic Engineering. (K. Carper, ed.). New York:
Elsevier, pp. 101–129.
H OOGSTRATE , A. & S PEK , A. 2002 Monte Carlo simulation and inference in accident
reconstruction. presented at. 5th International Conference on Forensic Statistics. Venice.
H OWSON , C. 1993 Personalistic Bayesianism. Philosophy of Probability. (J.-P. Dubucs, ed.).
Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 1–12.
J ENSEN , F. 1996 An Introduction to Bayesian Networks. New York: Springer.
KOST , G. & W ERNER , S. 1994 Use of Monte Carlo simulation techniques in accident
reconstruction. SAE Technical Paper 940719,. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.
L EWIS , D. 1973 Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
L EWIS , D. 1976 Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review,
85, 297–315.
L EWIS , D. 1980 A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. Studies in Inductive Logic and
Probability, Vol. II. (R. Jeffrey, ed.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 263–294.
L IMPERT , R. 1989 Motor Vehicle Accident Reconstruction and Cause Analysis, 3rd edn.
Charlottesville, VA: Michie Co.
L INDLEY , D. 1991 Subjective probability, decision analysis and their legal consequences. J. Roy.
Statist. Soc. A, 154, 83–92.
M C L EAN , J., A NDERSON , R., FARMER , M., L EE , B. & B ROOKS , C. 1994 Vehicle Travel
Speeds and the Incidence of Fatal Pedestrian Crashes, Road Accident Research Unit. Adelaide:
University of Adelaide.
NCUTLO, 1992 Uniform Vehicle Code and Model Traffic Ordinance. Evanston, IL: National
Committee on Uniform Laws and Ordinances.
N EPTUNE , J., F LYNN , J., C HAVEZ , P. & U NDERWOOD , H. 1995 Speed from skids: A modern
approach. Accident Reconstruction: Technology and Animation V. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.,
pp. 189–204.
N IEDERER , P. 1991 The accuracy and reliability of accident reconstruction. Automotive Engineering
and Litigation, Vol. 4. (G. Peters & G. Peters, eds). New York: Wiley, pp. 257–303.
P EARL , J. 2000 Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
P OOLE , D. & R AFTERY , A. 2000 Inference for deterministic simulation models: The Bayesian
melding approach. J. Amer. Statist. Assoc., 95, 1244–1255.
R EED , W. & K ESKIN , A. 1989 Vehicular deceleration and its relationship to friction. SAE Technical
Paper 890736. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.
BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS
87
ROAD T RAFFIC ACT 1991 Her Majesty’s Stationery Office. London.
ROSE , N., F ENTON , S. & H UGHES , C. 2001 Integrating Monte Carlo simulation, momentumbased impact modeling, and restitution data to analyze crash severity. SAE Technical Paper
2001-01-3347. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.
RUDRAM , D. & L AMBOURN , R. 1981 The scientific investigation of road accidents. Journal of
Occupational Accidents, 3, 177–185.
S CHOCKENHOFF , G., A PPEL , H. & R AU , H. 1985 Representation of actual reconstruction
methods for car-to-car accidents as confirmed by crash tests. SAE Technical Paper 850066.
Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.
S CHUM , D. 2000 Singular evidence and probabilistic reasoning in judicial proof. Harmonisation in
Forensic Expertise, Thela Thesis. (J. Nijboer & W. Sprangers, eds). pp. 587–603.
S PIEGELHALTER , D., T HOMAS , A. & B EST , N. 2000 WinBUGS Version 1.3 User Manual. Oxford:
MRC Biostatistics Unit, Oxford University.
S TALNAKER , R. 1968 A theory of conditionals. American Philosophical Monograph Series #2. (N.
Rescher, ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
S TEWART-M ORRIS , M. 1995 Real time, accurate recall, and other myths. Forensic Accident
Investigation: Motor Vehicles. (T. Bohan & A. Damask, eds). Charlottesville, VA: Michie
Butterworth, pp. 413–438.
TARONI , F., A ITKEN , C. & G ARBOLINO , P. 2001 De Finetti’s subjectivism, the assessment
of probabilities and the evaluation of evidence: A commentary for forensic scientists. Science
and Justice, 41, 145–150.
T RAFFIC I NSTITUTE 1946 Accident Investigation Manual. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Traffic Institute.
W OOD , D. & O’R IORDAIN , S. 1994 Monte Carlo simulation methods applied to accident
reconstruction and avoidance analysis. Accident Reconstruction: Technology and Animation
IV. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc., pp. 129–136.
Appendix A. WinBUGS code for Bayesian reconstruction of two-vehicle collision in
Fricke (1990)
model momentum
#Fricke 1990 Momentum Example; English units
{
# counterfactual world(s)
for (I in 1:M) {
u2.star[i]