Primavera De Filippi
European University Institute, Florence, Italy
pdefilippi@gmail.com
COPYRIGHT IN THE DIGITAL
ENVIRONMENT FROM INTELLECTUAL
PROPERTY TO VIRTUAL PROPERTY
Abstract: In recent years, copyright law has been subject to a series of legislative reforms aimed
at preserving the self-regulating feature of the copyright regime in the digital environment.
However, as the law does no longer reflect their expectations, a growing number of right holders
are relying on private ordering in order to adjust the default provisions of the copyright regime
with a variety of contractual means. Within the digital environment, the establishment of an
alternative regime of property rights could however facilitate the exploitation and the
dissemination of digital works, allowing for the copyright owners to maintain a certain level of
control over the exploitation of theirs works while simultaneously decreasing the level of
discrepancies that may occur between copyright law and property law. The regime would
distinguish between the copyright protection granted to the work as an intellectual creation and
the specific terms and conditions governing the exploitation of any given instance of the work,
into which the copyright owner could introduce a series of restrictions and/or obligations
enforceable erga omnes. Digital works would therefore become more akin to virtual goods and
could be alienated independently of any contractual relationship, thereby allowing for the market
for information goods to develop with fewer constraints.
Keywords: Property Law, copyright law
1. Introduction
Internet and digital technologies have seriously jeopardized the efficacy of
copyright law, which has now been reformed to face the challenges of the
digital environment. The legislative reform has however been strongly criticized
for introducing a new technological and legislative framework, potentially
incompatible with the traditional ratio of the copyright regime. Even assuming
the traditional ratio of copyright had survived, the question remains: Should the
rules governing the physical world be replicated in the digital environment or
would it be more sensible to adopt a different approach that would account for
the distinctive advantages of digital technologies?
In addressing the question, the paper performs a preliminary analysis of the
economic justifications of copyright law and subsequently explores the different
79
attempts that have been made in order to restore the self-regulating features of
the copyright regime into the digital environment. In particular, the employment
of DRM systems to broaden the scope of copyright protection and the use of
Open Content licenses to reduce the default level of protection might suggest
that the copyright regime has become inappropriate in the digital environment,
as a large number of right holders must incur additional transaction costs to
modify the scope and the extent of copyright protection they have been granted
with.
The paper proposes an alternative approach, combining the advantages of
both mechanisms while also taking advantage of the opportunities of the digital
environment. It advocates for the establishment of an alternative regime of
property rights allowing for the owner of the copyright in a work to incorporate
a series of rules into the digital manifestation of the work by the means of
specific rights and obligations intrinsically connected to the digital products and
enforceable erga omnes. Under this scheme, digital works would therefore
acquire the characteristics of virtual goods, allowing for the further
development of the market for information goods, in particular, through the
reintroduction of the doctrine of exhaustion into the digital environment.
Creative works, like any other information goods, share the two basic
characteristics of a public good: they are both non-excludable and non-rival in
consumption.1 In order to achieve an optimal allocation of resources, the
production and the exploitation of creative works must therefore be regulated in
such a way as to strike a balance between incentives to produce and access to
information.2
On the one hand, in view of the non-excludable nature of information
goods, there is the risk that, without an established system of rewards, authors
will create only a suboptimal quantity of works.3 This might impose a welfare
loss on society to the extent that certain works may not be produced although it
would be socially valuable to do so.4 The main goal of copyright law is thus to
1 For more details on the characteristics of information as a public good, see VARIAN, H. R. (1998)
Markets for Information Goods. University of California, Berkeley, CA.
2 The copyright regime must establish a trade-off between maximizing the incentive to create (dynamic
efficiency) and maximizing the benefits resulting from the creation of additional works (static efficiency). See
LÉVÊQUE, F. & MÉNIÈRE, Y. (2004) The Economics of Patents and Copyright, Paris, The Berkeley
Electronic Press.
See OAKLAND, W. H. (1974) Public Goods, Perfect Competition, and Underproduction. The Journal of
Political Economy, 82.
3
The consumption of information goods can be regarded as a prisoner’s dilemma, where every player is
likely to free-ride on the contribution of others without themselves providing any sort of contribution. For
more details, see GORDON, W. J. (1992) Asymmetric Market Failure and Prisoner's Dilemma in Intellectual
Property. University of Dayton Law Review, 17.
4
80
provide incentives for authors to create a socially optimal quantity of works, an
objective which is achieved through the granting of a bundle of exclusive rights
enabling authors to exercise a certain amount of control over the commercial
exploitation of their works so as to eventually secure economic rewards for their
creative endeavors.
On the other hand, however, the copyright regime creates a situation of
artificial scarcity, which might prevent the maximization of social welfare5 in so
far as certain users will be excluded from enjoying a work even where the
exploitation thereof would not impose any additional costs on society.
Copyright law must therefore introduce a number of limitations on the exclusive
rights granted to every copyright owner,6 in order to ensure the maximum
availability of works to every member of society.
As it creates a trade-off between static and dynamic efficiency, the
copyright regime is however an imperfect mechanism for the regulation of
creative works, since it is unable to simultaneously maximize both the
production and the accessibility of works.7 Alternative mechanisms could be
developed under the form of governmental taxes or subsidies, in order to
provide adequate incentives for authors to create without unduly restraining the
possibilities for users to access and to exploit their works. 8 While this might
eliminate the deadweight loss on society, the introduction of a system of
5
In a situation of perfect competition, the price of a good equals its marginal costs and the good is
produced up to the point where the demand meets the function of marginal costs (the socially efficient
quantity). In a situation of monopoly, instead, given a specific demand function, the monopolist will produce
only to the point where marginal revenues equal marginal costs (the first order condition for profit
maximization). For a more detailed analysis of the deadweight loss resulting from the introduction of a
temporary monopoly within the copyright regime, see LANDES, W. M. & POSNER, R. A. (1989) An
Economic Analysis of Copyright Law. The Journal of Legal Studies, 18.
6
As creative works constitute both the input and the output of creative endeavor, the term of copyright
protection should be limited to the point in time where the marginal benefits resulting from the increase in
copyright protection are equal to the marginal cost to be incurred for the production of new works (see e.g.
VARIAN, H. R. (2005) Copying and Copyright. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19.) and the scope of
protection should be restrained so as to ensure that certain exploitations of a work will not be undermined by
any imperfection of the market. In particular, whenever a socially valuable exploitation is likely to be
prevented as a result of market failure (e.g. excessive transaction costs), the unauthorized exploitation of the
work should nevertheless be allowed. See e.g. GORDON, W. J. (1982) Fair Use as Market Failure: A
Structural and Economic Analysis of the "Betamax" Case and its Predecessors. Columbia Law Review, 82.
For a more detailed analysis of the access/incentives trade-off of copyright law, see: LANDES, W. M. &
POSNER, R. A. (2003) The Economic Structure of Intellectual Property Law, Cambridge, Massachusetts,
The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
7
See e.g. FISHER, W. (2004) An Alternative Compensation System. Promises to Keep: Technology, Law
and the Future of Entertainment. Stanford University Press.
8
81
taxation is however likely to distort the economy in so far as it would
unconditionally decrease the level of resources that could otherwise be
employed in other fields of activity.9 Besides, markets rewards are believed to
be more efficient than taxes or subsidies, because, in the absence of market
failures, the law of the supply and demand enables the market to appreciate
every work for the real value it conveys to society.10
Another important goal of the copyright regime is therefore that of
promoting the trade of creative works by allowing for the development of a
market for information goods. An indispensable precondition for a market for
information goods to emerge is however the creation of a precisely defined set
of property rights, since there can be no market as long as there are no objects
of trade. The exclusive rights of the copyright regime constitute thus a means by
which authors are endowed with a set of proprietary rights over their artistic
creations. Although they relate to the intangible expression of a work, the
exclusive rights granted to the owners of the copyright in a work allow them to
dispose of their works as if they were tangible assets which can therefore be
exploited like any other type of property.11
According to the Coase theorem,12 in a situation without transaction costs,
the divisibility and free alienability of property rights is likely to promote the
most efficient allocation of resources, because every asset will be acquired
and/or exploited by the party for which it is the most valuable. If transaction
costs are to be taken into account, the initial entitlement of rights becomes
however relevant, since excessive transaction costs could preclude certain
transactions from occurring. An optimal allocation of resources may
consequently only be achieved if the copyright is constructed in such a way as
to reduce transaction costs to the minimum.13
9
For a detailed analysis of the pro and the cons of remunerating authors by way of governmental
subsidies, see e.g. LIEBOWITZ, S. (2003) Alternative Copyright Systems: The Problem with a Compulsory
License. SERCIAC.
10 According to neoclassical economics, in a situation of perfect competition, the market price of a product
constitutes the best indication of the value assigned to the product by society as a whole. See BROWN, T.
C. (1984) The Concept of Value in Resource Allocation. Land Economics, 60.
For an analysis of the extent to which the transfer of intellectual property rights is subject to the same
rules governing the transfer of property rights in tangible goods, see SCHRAMM, F. B. (1960) Licenses,
Contracts and Assignments of Intellectual Property. Cleveland-Marshall Law Review, 9.
11
12
See COASE, R. H. (1960) The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3.
By giving authors the initial entitlement to exclude others from exploiting their works, the copyright
regime ensures that transaction costs are minimized, since, if the author had to enter into an agreement with
every user who may subsequently come into possession of the work, transactions costs may become so
high that the work may never be created in the first place. See GORDON, W. J. & BONE, R. G. (2000)
Copyright. IN BOUCKAERT, B. & GEEST, G. D. (Eds.) Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. Cheltenham,
13
82
2. The Object of the Copyright
A proper definition of the scope of copyright protection requires an accurate
identification of the subject matter involved. However, while the law provides a
series of indications with regard to what constitutes a work of authorship for the
purpose of the copyright regime,14 the identification of the various components
of a work remains ultimately ambiguous. Accordingly, before addressing the
specific characteristics of the copyright regime, four core entities (work,
expression, manifestation, and item)15 are to be properly identified, and the
relationships that exist amongst them be precisely established.
In particular, a work of authorship can only be defined as a general concept
or idea. The work as such has no physical subsistence and it is therefore
imperative that the work be distinguished from the physical item into which it is
being conveyed, which is a mere representation of the work.16 However, the
concept of a work as an intellectual entity is also to be distinguished from the
expression it has been articulated into, which represents the actual content of the
Edward Elgar. The optimal allocation of rights, however, does not only refer to the initial entitlement of rights,
but also to the proper definition thereof. In fact, if the scope of the exclusive rights granted to the copyright
owner is too broad, certain users may be precluded from enjoying a work because of the excessive
transaction costs that would otherwise be involved.
The subject matter which may qualify for copyright protection varies from one jurisdiction to another,
although a number of international instruments have been developed in order to harmonize the national
copyright regimes, such as, in particular, the Berne Convention of 1886 for the Protection of Literary and
Artistic Works, which requires that copyright protection be granted to any artistic, literary, musical and
dramatic work (Article 2) and the Rome Convention of 1961, which extend copyright protection to
performers, producers of phonograms and broadcasting organizations. In addition, computer software has
universally become eligible for protection as a literary work (see article 10(1) of the TRIPs Agreement),
semiconductors and integrated circuits may qualify for protection under the copyright regime of certain
jurisdictions (see e.g. the European Directive 87/54/EEC on the Legal Protection of Semiconductor and the
Semiconductor Chip Protection Act of 1984 in the USA) and, in Europe, sui-generis rights have been
introduced for the protection of certain databases (see the European Directive 96/9/EC on the legal
protection of databases).
14
These four entities (world, expression, manifestation, and item) constitute the basic entities of the
Functional Requirement for Bibliographic Records (FRBR) model, endorsed by the International Federation
of Library Associations and Institutions (IFLA) to provide a clear, precisely stated and commonly shared
understanding of the nature and purpose of bibliographic records, for the future development of a common
framework for bibliographic metadata.
15
16
See LUBETZKY, S. (1961) The Function of the Main Entry in Alphabetical Catalogue - One Approach.
IN SVENONIUS, E. & MCGARRY, D. (Eds.) Seymour Lubetzky: Writings on the Classical Art of
Cataloguing. Englewood, CO, Libraries Unlimited. LUBETZKY, S. (1969) Principles of Cataloging. Final
Report. Phase I: Descriptive Cataloging. IN SVENONIUS, E. & MCGARRY, D. (Eds.) Seymour Lubetzky:
Writings on the Classical Art of Cataloging. Englewood, CO, Libraries Unlimited.
83
work. Indeed, a work can be articulated into an unlimited number of different
expressions, which, in spite of their differences, all constitute an expressive
representation of the very same work.17
The expression of a work fundamentally consists of a particular set of signs
ensuing from the concretization of the conceptual idea of the work into a
particular entity with an objectively recognizable structure.18 Although
inherently immaterial, the expression of a work cannot therefore come into
existence without any underlying physical carrier, as the expression of an
abstract idea inevitably requires a medium on which it can be formulated
(taking into account that the human brain may qualify as a carrier of
information for human memory). As such, however, the expression of a work is
completely independent from the specific physical carrier it has been expressed
into, and a single expression may therefore subsist on more than one carrier
simultaneously, to the extent that they all constitute a similar medium of
expression.
The expression of a work is thus to be discerned from the manifestation of
the work, which basically amounts to the recording of an expression into a
particular format that can be subsequently published into a particular medium.
Different recordings of an identical expression (e.g. different typographical
arrangements, alternative page layouts, etc) would therefore automatically give
rise to different manifestations. Although it refers to a tangible embodiment of
the work, the manifestation does not however amount to the item as such.
Devoid of any physical subsistence, the manifestation of a work is a general
concept which comprises all the representations of a work with identical
characteristics and physical appearance,19 whereas, the item, as a tangible
According to Elaine Svenonius, a major contributor to the field of information organization and
cataloging, a work can be defined as "the set of all documents that are copies of (equivalent to) a particular
document (an individual document chosen as emblematic of the work, normally its first instance) or related
to this individual by revision, update, abridgment, enlargement, or translation." SVENONIUS, E. (2000) The
Intellectual Foundations of Information Organization, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
17
18
For instance, if a work has been expressed into a text, the expression will refer to the specific words,
sentences, and paragraphs that constitute that text, whereas, if a work has been expressed into music, the
expression will refer to the particular notes that constitute the melody. For more details on the distinction
between a work and the expression of a work, see IFLA (1998) Functional Requirements for Bibliographic
Records. IN SAUR, K. G. (Ed., IFLA Study Group on the Functional Requirements for Bibliographic
Records.
19
The manifestation of a work may refer to large variety of different materials, such as manuscripts,
books, magazines, photographs, paintings, drawings, sound recordings, video recordings, CD-roms, DVDroms, or any other physical embodiment. More precisely, according to the FRBR’s definition, the
manifestation “as an entity [...] represents all the physical objects that bear the same characteristics, in
respect to both intellectual content and physical form.” See Ibid.
84
carrier of information, essentially results from the fixation of a particular
manifestation into a tangible medium, which constitutes therefore a singular
instance of the work.
As a result, while the work, the expression and the manifestation thereof
may only be regarded as public goods (as they are intrinsically non-rival in
consumption and the benefits resulting from the exploitation thereof can
theoretically be enjoyed by anyone), the item into which they are being
incorporated may be regarded as either a private good or a public good,
according to whether it amounts to a material item or to a digital item. In
particular, while an item can be easily identified in the physical world, the
concept may turn out to be slightly controversial in the digital environment.
Strictly speaking, in fact, the transfer of a digital item would inevitably give rise
to a new entity (which necessarily resides on a different location in the physical
memory of a computer or other electronic device), although the two may
nevertheless be regarded as being identical for the purposes of copyright law. In
the digital environment, the concept of an item can therefore be properly
determined only when also taking into account the context into which the item
has to be identified.20 Accordingly, for the purpose of this paper, an item will be
defined as any tangible entity which represents a unique exemplary of one
particular manifestation of a work, taking into account that it is not necessary
for the tangible entity to remain physically the same, as long as it can be
logically identified as being the same.
3. Self-Regulating Mechanisms of Copyright Law
The role of the copyright regime is basically to realign the public nature of
the work with the private nature of the item into which it is being conveyed.21
By granting copyright owners with a series of exclusive rights which enable
them to exclude others from exploiting the work, the expression, and, to some
extent, the manifestation of the work, copyright law has in fact turned every
element of the work into a private good, so that both the work as an intellectual
creation and the tangible medium into which it is being conveyed can now be
disposed of as a single entity with a consistent set of properties.
20
See PASKIN, N. (2003) On Making and Identifying a Copy. D-Lib Magazine, 9.
21 For more details on the role of copyright law in reconciling the properties of the work as an intangible
entity with the properties of the tangible manifestation thereof, see BENTLEY, N. (2007) Trading Rights to
Digital Content. International Workshop for Technical, Economic and Legal Aspects of Business Models for
Virtual Goods. Koblenz, Germany.
85
Until the advent of digital technologies, this mechanism has been relatively
successful. In fact, by linking the expression of a work to the physical
manifestation thereof, copyright law created a self-regulating environment
which was capable of dissuading the majority of end-users from illegitimately
reproducing a work in so far as the medium it had been embodied into could not
itself be easily reproduced.22
The process of digitization has however turned the medium itself into an
intangible entity, which does no longer possess any of the physical mechanisms
of excludability characteristics of tangible goods and may thus no longer be
regarded as a scarce resource.23 The digital instance of a work can thus be
regarded as a public good, since it has become virtually non-excludable (given
that, as every user becomes a potential supplier of the work, the possibility for
the copyright owner to exclude users from enjoying a work decreases with the
number of users who have already come into possession of the work) and nonrival in consumption (since, if a digital work can be reproduced immediately
and at virtually no costs, two or more individuals can consume the same work
without affecting each other‘s consumption).24
While this may bring a number of advantages to certain right holders and
end-users,25 digitization is however likely to eliminate the self-regulatory
features of the copyright regime by destroying the link that had been established
between the work (which has been turned into a private good by copyright law)
and the corresponding instances of the work (which have been turned into a
public good by the means of digital technologies). Consequently, the properties
of the work are once again misaligned with the properties of the medium into
which it is being conveyed to the public.
22 The properties of the physical world constitute a natural barrier to copyright infringement, which is more
likely to be confined to a small number of commercial infringers. See, e.g. DAVIS, R. (2000) The Digital
Dilemma: Intellectual Property in the Information Age, Washington, National Academy Press.
23 For more details on the impact of the digital technologies on the enforceability of copyright law, see e.g.
HALPERN, S. W. (2001) The Digital Threat to the Normative Role of Copyright Law. Ohio State Law
Journal, 62.
For more details on the public good nature of digital goods, see RAYNA, T. (2007) Digital goods as
public durable goods. Department of Economics. Université Aix-Marseille III.
24
The changes introduced by Internet and digital technologies have promoted the development of new
business models which can take advantage of the new digital framework. See, e.g. TAPSCOTT, D.,
TICOLL, D. & LOWY, A. (2000) Digital Capital: Harnessing the Power of Business Webs, Harward Business
School Press. For more information on the specific features of direct and indirect e-commerce, see, inter
alia: RAYPORT, J. F. & JAWORSKI, B. (2002) Introduction to e-Commerce, McGraw-Hill. BAKOS, Y. (2001)
The Emerging Landscape for Retail E-Commerce. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15. CHOI, S. Y. &
WHINSTON, A. B. (1999) The future of e-commerce: integrate and customize. IEEE Computer, 31.
25
86
4. Private Mechanisms of Self-Help
Since copyright law may no longer be able to achieve its primary objective
in the digital environment, additional contractual and/or technological
instruments have been developed as an attempt to re-establish the selfregulating features of the copyright regime by way of private ordering.26
In line with the principles of freedom of contract, according to which
anyone may enter into an agreement on private terms in order to pursue
individual interests, the default level of protection provided by the copyright
regime can theoretically be complemented or eventually superseded by
contractual means,27 whose provisions may sometimes be enforced by
technological measures.28 In particular, Digital Rights Management (DRM)
systems and Open Content licenses are two mechanisms which are being
increasingly employed for the release of copyright works into the digital
environment. Both are basically aimed at refining the default rule of the
copyright regime (albeit in a very divergent manner) so as to make it more
consistent with the new framework established by the digital technologies.
DRM systems have been conceived with the intent to replicate the
properties of a private good into the digital manifestation of a work. In fact, just
as they can emulate the characteristic of excludability by the means of specific
technological measures of protection aimed at preventing the unauthorized
access to a work, DRM systems are also capable of creating a situation of
artificial scarcity through the combination of hardware and/or software devices
specifically designed to preclude the illegitimate reproduction of the work and
any further distribution thereof.29 DRM systems may therefore greatly facilitate
See COHEN, J. E. (1998) Copyright and the Jurisprudence of Self-Help. Berkeley Technology Law
Journal, 13.
26
Not only can the owners of the copyright in a work specify the exact subject matter of the transaction,
but they may also introduce additional rights and obligations which have not been provided for by the
relevant intellectual property laws. Enforcing the terms and conditions under which a creative work has been
licensed may thus eventually be more a matter of contract law than a matter of copyright law. See
MERGES, R. P. (1997) The End of Friction? Property Rights and Contract in the 'Newtonian' World of OnLine Commerce. Ibid.12.
27
See ESKICLOGLU, A. M. (2004) Protecting Intellectual Property in Digital Multimedia Networks.
Computer, 36.
28
See e.g. ESKICIOGLU, A. M. & DELP, E. J. (2001) An overview of multimedia content protection in
consumer electronics devices. Signal Processing: Image Communication. Elsevier. BECHTOLD, S. (2004)
Digital Rights Management in the United States and Europe. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 52.
For a comprehensive analysis of the technological aspects of Digital Rights Management systems, see
chapter 2 in BECKER, E., BUHSE, W., GÜNNEWIG, D. & RUMP, N. (2004) Digital Rights Management:
Technological, Economic, Legal and Political Aspects, Springer.
29
87
the trading of digital works by reconciling the properties inherent to the digital
instance of a work with the properties that every original work of authorship has
been granted with under copyright law.
However, DRM systems are usually employed in the context of particular
licensing schemes, where what is being sold is not the digital instance of a work
but only the right to use the work under the specific terms and conditions of the
license. Moreover, to the extent that DRM systems are likely to feature a
number of restrictions which extend beyond the scope of the copyright regime, 30
the properties of the work and of the digital manifestation thereof may end up
being once again misaligned.
Conversely, Open Content licenses31 are mainly aimed at realigning the
legal properties of the work as an intellectual creation with the physical
properties of the digital manifestation thereof by reducing the scope of
copyright protection and thereby reintroducing some of the public good
characteristics originally pertaining to the work.32 Although ultimately relying
Copyright owners can release their works under very restrictive terms and conditions which are likely to
extend beyond the scope of the copyright regime and which may eventually bypass some of the statutory
limitations of copyright law and which can be automatically enforced by technological means. For more
details, see ELKIN-KOREN, N. (2001) The Privatization of Information Policy. Ethics and Information
Technology, 2.
30
The term Open Content refers to certain typologies of copyright licensing agreements which are
designed to increase the liberties of end-users. For a general overview of the different Open Content
licenses, see LIANG, L. (2004) Guide to Open Content Licenses. Piet Zwart Institute.
31
One the one hand, Open Content licensing is aimed at eliminating some of the copyright restrictions so
as to turn the work back into a non-rival good. In particular, Open Content licenses have been designed to
encourage the free reproduction of a licensed work, either in whole or in part. Moreover, although the
distribution and/or the making available of the work may sometimes be subject to certain requirements of
form (by requiring, for instance, that proper attribution be given and that the licensing terms under which a
work has been released be readily available), Open Content licenses cannot impose any restrictions upon
the distribution and/or the making available of a work. See e.g. the Open Knowledge definition at
http://www.opendefinition.org and the definition of the Free Cultural Works at http://freedomdefined.org. On
the other hand, Open Content licensing may also eliminate the artificial excludability established by
copyright law and/or technological means. For instance, certain Open Content licenses are incompatible
with the application of technological measures of protections to the extent that they prevent or restrict the
access to and/or the legitimate exploitation of a work (see e.g. the Creative Commons licenses), whereas
others are incompatible with the application of any technological measures of protection as such, whether or
not they have been designed to prevent or restrict the legitimate exploitation of a work (see e.g. the AntiDRM license and the GNU Free Documentation License). Moreover, a number of Open Content licenses
expressly preclude the commercial distribution of a work (see e.g. the non-commercial clause of the
Creative Commons licenses), so that access to the work may not be conditional to the payment of a fee.
Besides, even where the commercial exploitation of a work is allowed, the terms and conditions of the
license, according to which the work can be freely reproduced and redistributed to anyone, cannot be
modified by the licensee (see e.g. article 4(a) of the Creative Commons licenses: “You may distribute,
32
88
on the copyright regime, Open Content license are in fact using the law in order
to create a series of positive rights (as opposed to the traditional exclusive
rights) to ensure the public availability and the free dissemination of the
content.
As a general rule, Open Content licenses could be regarded as instant
licenses.33 The terms and conditions under which a work can be exploited are in
fact incorporated into the work and the licenses provide that anyone coming
into possession of the work be automatically granted with a new license to
exploit the work in accordance with the corresponding licensing terms. As such,
however, the license does not attach to any particular instance of the work but
only to the particular user thereof, and a new license has therefore to be created
every time the item is being transferred to a new user.34
The advent of Internet and digital technologies has disrupted the traditional
equilibrium of the copyright regime, allowing for the reproduction of digital
content to be performed at very low costs and without any quality loss, and for
the distribution thereof to be achieved instantaneously and on a worldwide
scale.35 In order to ensure long-term viability of the copyright regime in the
digital environment, copyright law has therefore been reformed, but only to the
publicly display, publicly perform, or publicly digitally perform the Work only under the terms of this License”)
and the majority of Open Content licenses generally prevent the licensee from imposing further restrictions
on the rights granted by the license (see e.g. article 4(a) of the Creative Commons licenses: “You may not
offer or impose any terms on the Work that alter or restrict the terms of this License or the recipients'
exercise of the rights granted hereunder”). All users subsequently coming into possession of the work will
therefore be entitled to redistribute the work for free, whether or not they originally had to pay for it.
See e.g. FRIPP, C. (2005) Instant licences move copyright into a new digital space: is it time to
encourage Copyright Cannibals? 8th Symposium on Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Sydney, Australia.
33
Note, however, that in order to facilitate the maximum dissemination of works, Open Content licenses
automatically grant a new license to anyone that come into possession of the work regardless of the
approval of the licensor (see e.g. article 8(a) of the Creative Commons licenses, according to which every
time a licensee distributes or publicly digitally performs the work, the licensor offers to the recipient a license
to the work on the same terms and conditions).
34
Copyright infringement is a function of the benefits deriving from copyright infringement and the costs of
infringement. On the one hand, in the digital environment, the costs of copyright infringement has drastically
(see e.g. LEE, G. B. (1996) Addressing Anonymous Messages in Cyberspace. Harvard Journal of
Computer-Mediated Communication, 2.) and the public does not necessarily regard the illegitimate
reproduction and dissemination of digital content as a criminal activity (see LITMAN, J. (1994) The Exclusive
Right to Read. Cardozo Arts & Entertainment Law Journal, 13.) On the other hand, copyright enforcement
on the Internet has become particularly difficult (see DAVIS, R. (2000) The Digital Dilemma: Intellectual
Property in the Information Age, Washington, National Academy Press.) in particular, in view of the
discrepancies existing within the different national copyright systems which may pose a series of challenges
to the international resolution of copyright disputes. See GOLDSTEIN, P. (2001) International Copyright:
Principles, Law, and Practice, Oxford University Press.
35
89
extent necessary as to restore the former status quo. Accordingly, while the
WIPO Copyright Treaty (WCT) endorsed the deployment of DRM systems by
extending the scope of copyright protection to certain technological measures of
protection36 and to any information incorporated into a copyright work and
necessary for the correct operation of DRM systems,37 the legal status of Open
Content licenses has however not yet been recognized by any jurisdiction (with
the exception of France)38 and the validity and/or enforceability thereof is
therefore still subject to debate.39
The fundamental question is whether it is indeed efficient to reintroduce
into the digital environment a scheme which replicates the very same rules that
govern the physical world, or whether it would be more appropriate to establish
an alternative regime for digital works, which would replicate as closely as
possible the characteristics of the physical world while nevertheless accounting
The WIPO Copyright Treaty (WCT), adopted in 1996 in Geneva, has introduced an additional layer of
protection against the circumvention of particular technological measures of protection. See article 11 of the
WCT, as implemented in the USA by the Digital Millennium Copyright Act of 1999, section 1201, and in the
European Community by the Directive 2001/29/EC on the harmonization of certain aspects of copyright and
related rights in the information society, article 6.
36
37
See article 12(1) of the WIPO Copyright Treaty.
38
The French Copyright Code has recently been reformed as a result of the enactment of the DADVSI
law (Law N.2006-961 of 1 August 2006 on copyright and related rights in the information society) and now
specifically provides for the possibility to license the copyright in a work without any consideration to be
given in return. See e.g. Article L.122-7-1 of the French Code de la propriété intellectuelle, according to
which authors are free to make their works freely available to the public, subject to the rights of possible coauthors or third parties and in compliance with the agreement they have concluded (emphasis added).
39
The legal nature and the efficacy of the various typologies of Open Content licenses is difficult to
ascertain, mostly because there have been so far only a few judicial precedents addressing the actual legal
status of Open Content licenses. This notwithstanding, the validity of the Creative Commons licenses has
recently been addressed in Spain first in the case of SGAE v Luis (Audiencia Provincial de Pontevedra,
Sentencia de 29 Nov. 2005, rec. 3008/2005), where the court held that the licenses were invalid because
they lacked a signature, and later in the case of SGAE v Fernandez (Juzgade de Primera Instancia de
Badajoz, Procedimento Ordinaria 761/2005, Sentencia N. 15/2006), where the court eventually
acknowledged the efficacy of the licenses as a valid legal instrument, although the court did not further
investigate upon their legal nature. Moreover, in the Netherlands, not only did the case of Curry v Audax
(District Court of Amsterdam, Case no. 334492 / KG 06-176 SR) confirm the validity of the Creative
Commons licenses, but it also endorsed the enforceability of their corresponding terms and conditions.
Whether any given Open Content license should be regarded as a bare license or as a contract remains
however an important question, which may affect not only the manner in which the provisions of the license
may be interpreted, but also the extent to which the various terms and conditions can be enforced and the
nature of the remedies available upon breach. For more details on the difficulty to determine the legal status
of Open Content licenses, see HIETANEN, H. (2007) A License or a Contract: Analyzing the Nature of
Creative Commons Licenses. Helsinki Institute for Information Technology.
90
of the various benefits that the digital environment may offer so as to take
advantage thereof.
There exist in fact a number of drawbacks in the current copyright regime,
which may perhaps be resolved with a legislative reform that would better
account of the opportunities provided by the digital technologies.
To begin with, the copyright is a proprietary right vesting in the expression
of a work, which must however coexist with the property rights vesting into
every tangible instance of the work. A series of discrepancies may however
arise between the regime of copyright law and the regime of property law, given
that the exclusive rights of the copyright regime fundamentally impinges upon
the exercise of property rights in physical property.40 Accordingly, copyright
law may only allow for the establishment of a partial market for information
goods, since, by protecting the expression of a work with a series of proprietary
rights which are necessarily distinct from the rights vesting in the tangible
manifestation of the work, the copyright regime does not permit anyone to
freely dispose of the items they have legitimately purchased.41
Besides, a proper market for information goods may be unable to emerge in
the digital environment because the sale of a digital work is generally framed as
a mere licensing of rights, rather than as an actual transfer of ownership. 42
Moreover, even if ownership were granted, digital items would nevertheless be
excluded from the doctrine of exhaustion,43 thereby drastically reducing the
40
The owner of the copyright in a work can prevent others from exploiting their property, to the extent that
doing so would infringe the copyright in the work. See KINSELLA, N. S. (2001) Against Intellectual Property.
Journal of Libertarian Studies, 15.
41 For instance, one may not draw on a painting which has been legitimately purchased in order to redistribute it on the market, because that would infringe upon the exclusive right to make derivative works.
Similarly, one may not display and/or communicate the work (albeit untouched) to the public, because that
would infringe upon the exclusive right of making available, nor can one rent a work which has been
previously purchased because the exclusive rental/lending right is not exhausted after the first sale of the
work.
The dissemination of works has developed into a system of access privileges imparted by the means of
copyright licenses which precisely stipulate the condition under which the work can be enjoyed. Copyright
owners are provided with a higher level of control over the exploitation of their works, which can be
preserved even after the works have been transmitted to the users. See ELKIN-KOREN, N. (1996)
Public/Private and Copyright Reform in Cyberspace. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication, 2.
42
43
The principle of exhaustion has been expressly excluded from the digital environment by the WIPO
Copyright Treaty, which allows for "the Contracting Parties to determine the conditions, if any, under which
the exhaustion of the right [of distribution] applies after the first sale […] of the original or a copy of the work
with the authorization of the author” but only with regard to "fixed copies that can be put into circulation as
tangible objects" (article 6 and Agreed statements concerning article 6).
91
opportunities for a free market in information goods to develop,44 despite it
being one of the primary justifications for the establishment of the copyright
regime.
5. A New Regime of Property Rights
One of the main challenges for the establishment of a market for
information goods is that every work may be subject to a variety of rights,
owned by a variety of right holders, so that any particular instance of the work
may not be unconditionally disposed of without first obtaining the consent from
all the right holders involved.45
As previously mentioned, a work is composed of different layers – namely,
the work as an intellectual creation, the expression as a particular realization of
the work, the manifestation as the actual embodiment of the expression into a
particular medium, and the item as a single exemplar of the manifestation. At
any of these layers, different rights pertaining to different right holders may be
recognized. In particular, although generally owned by the same entity, the
rights vesting in the expression of a work may be owned by someone other than
the holder of the rights in the work (e.g. in the case of translations or other
derivative works). Moreover, in any jurisdiction that recognizes protection in
the typographical arrangement of a published edition, the publisher would be
the owner of that copyright, although not necessarily the owner of the copyright
in the work or in the expression of the work. Finally the purchaser of an item of
the work will generally be the owner of the proprietary rights in that particular
copy, the exploitation of which may however be restrained by the rights vesting
in any other layer of the work.46
44
Since the doctrine of exhaustion does not apply to the digital environment, digital works cannot be
freely traded in the market for information goods, thereby reducing the overall availability of works, as well
as the affordability thereof. See REESE, R. A. (2003) The first sale doctrine in the era of digital networks.
Law and Economics Research Paper. University of Texas.
This situation has been described as the tragedy of the anticommons, which basically refers to the fact
that, whenever multiple owners hold an effective right of exclusion over a scarce resource, the resource may
be prone to underuse, in any case where collecting the different rights into a useful set of property rights
would be too expensive and/or excessively time consuming. For more details, see: HELLER, M. A. (1998)
The Tragedy of the Anticommons: Property in the Transition from Marx to Markets. Harvard Law Review,
111.
45
See e.g. GINSBURG, J. C. (1992) Conflicts of Copyright Ownership Between Authors and Owners of
Original Artworks: An Essay in Comparative and International Private Law. Columbia Journal of Law & the
Arts, 17.
46
92
The proposed reform is based on a clear distinction between the rights
vesting in the work, in the expression, and in the manifestation of the work, and
those pertaining to each individual instance of the work. In particular, although
copyright law protects the expression of every original work of authorship with
a bundle of exclusive rights, every instance of the work may be subject to a
different set of rights, the scope and the extent of which are ultimately
determined by the respective right holders. Accordingly, as a general rule,
every time the copyright owner incorporates a work into a specific medium and
releases it under specific terms and conditions, that particular instance of the
work will basically only inherit those rights which have been specifically
selected from the default bundle of rights vesting in the expression of the
work.47 However, as opposed to the various contractual agreements upon which
both DRM systems and Open Content licenses are based, under the proposed
scheme, the various prohibitions and/or permissions pertaining to any given
instance of a work would be automatically incorporated into the digital item
under a proprietary scheme48 and the level of copyright protection granted to
every digital instance of a work would ultimately depend upon the choices
made by the copyright owner at the moment in which the item has been created.
Under the proposed regime, therefore, the digital manifestation of a work
would not necessarily be governed by the standard provisions of the copyright
regime. In particular, while the default level of protection granted to any digital
work would be the same as the one granted to any tangible work, as long as they
are not fully satisfied with the default provisions of copyright law, right holders
would be given the opportunity to reduce and/or to expand upon the scope of
copyright protection by incorporating a number of permissions and/or
restrictions into every digital instance of a work, so as to regulate the overall
exploitation thereof.
Copyright owners would therefore not be deprived of any of the rights
vesting in the work, in the expression or in the manifestation of the work.
Right holders may release their works under particular licensing terms, either by the means of particular
technological measures of protection which automatically enforce the terms of the contractual agreement, or
by way of instant licenses which automatically apply to the content into which they have been incorporated.
The contractual license under which the instance of a work has been released thus fundamentally becomes
an integral part of the product, as the various term and conditions collapse into the work so as to produce a
new product whose specific characteristics ultimately depend upon the terms of the license. For more details
on the concept of contract as product, see RADIN, M. J. (2000) Humans, Computers, and Binding
Commitment. Indiana Law Journal, 75.
47
While contract law creates rights and obligations in personam, which can only be enforced between the
parties to the contract, copyright law establishes a series of exclusive rights which are governed under a
property rule and are enforceable erga omnes. See ELKIN-KOREN, N. (1997) Copyright Policy and the
Limits of Freedom of Contract. Berkeley Technology Law Journal, 12.
48
93
Instead, in the digital environment, the copyright in a work would ultimately
amount to the exclusive right to determine the nature and the scope of the rights
vesting in every digital instance of the work. These rights would distinguish
themselves from the standard model of property rights to the extent that they
could be refined with a number of rights and obligations governing the manner
in which and the extent to which any given instance of work can be legitimately
exploited. Rather than as a contractual instrument, the various terms and
conditions regulating the exploitation of the work would therefore be regarded
as a series of restrictive covenants, the number, the nature and the extent of
which would basically depend upon the way in which the proprietary rights
have been framed at the moment in which the digital work has been created.49
Once they have been assigned to a particular instance of the work, in fact,
the new typologies of property rights would become forever bound with the
digital item and could no longer be modified. Consequently, by the mere fact of
obtaining a digital copy of the work, users would automatically acquire the right
to exploit it in accordance with the terms and conditions under which it has
been released but only insofar as the exploitation is confined to that particular
instance of the work which has been legitimately obtained, as it would
otherwise infringe the copyright in the work.50
The rights and obligations governing the manner in which a digital work can be legitimately exploited
would become inherently connected with that particular item of the work, i.e. they would run with the item in
the same way as servitudes and/or restrictive covenants run with the land. For more details on the possible
implementation of servitudes in personal property and, more particularly, in intellectual property rights, see
ROBINSON, G. O. (2003) Personal Property Servitudes. Law & Economics Research Papers. University of
Virginia School of Law.
49
Although the digital manifestation of a work may be freely exploited according to the specific terms and
conditions under which it has been released, the work as an intellectual creation would nevertheless be
protected by copyright law. In other words, the possession of a digital item incorporating a work protected by
copyright law would allow for anyone to exploit the work under certain conditions, but only to the extent that
the exploitation is confined to that particular instance of the work and does not extend to the work in general.
While users may be able to e.g. reproduce the digital work they have legally purchased, they may however
not reproduce the work into a different logical entity. For instance, if a user purchased a book in a particular
format which categorically prevents the book from being printed, the item may only be reproduced in the
very same format and with the very same restrictions as the original, whereas, the user has no right to
reproduce the work (i.e. the content of the book) into a text editor in order to save it into a different format.
Similarly, with regard to the right of distribution and the right of communication to the public, while the owner
of a digital work may be allowed to redistribute that particular instance of the work and/or communicate it to
the public, the distribution and/or the making available of the work as embodied into a different item would
nevertheless be condemned by copyright law. However, although, on the one hand, the reproduction, the
distribution and the making available of a work are inherently connected with a particular instance of the
work and it is therefore relatively easy to draw a line between what constitutes legitimate exploitation
(related to the digital item of the work) and illegitimate exploitation (related to the actual content of the work),
on the other hand, with regard to the exclusive right of adaptation, identifying the dividing line between what
50
94
Accordingly, the main distinction between the current model of copyright
law and the proposed regime for the digital environment is fundamentally that
the terms and conditions governing the exploitation of a work would no longer
be based on a contractual relationship between the copyright owner and the enduser, but would instead be inherent to the digital item they have been embodied
into and consequently acquire validity erga omnes.51 The terms and conditions
under which the work can be exploited would fundamentally amount to a series
of rights and obligations in rem,52 enforceable against anyone coming into
possession of that particular item of the work without the necessity to enter into
any contractual relationship with the corresponding copyright owner. The
enforceability of every provision will however necessarily be limited in
duration, since, once the copyright in the work has expired, the rights would
automatically revert back to standard property rights.53
is legitimate and what not may be slightly more controversial, since the right relates more to the expression
of the work than to the item per se. For instance, while users may be able to e.g. use a particular digital work
for the making of a derivative work by incorporating it (in whole or in part) into another digital work, the
making of a new work based upon the content of the original work would not be allowed, as it would
essentially relate to the expression of the work, in which the copyright subsists independently of the rights
vesting in any given instance of the work.
As opposed to contractual rights and obligations which can only be enforced inter partes, rights and
obligations with erga omnes effect can be enforced against everyone. An erga omnes right may thus create
an obligation for anyone to act in compliance with the content of the right. For instance, the copyright in a
work is an erga omnes right which creates an obligation for anyone not to reproduce, distribute or
communicate the work to the public, as well as not to make any derivative works based upon it. A copyright
license, conversely, is a mere contractual instrument, which is therefore unable to create obligations towards
all. Under the proposed regime, however, the copyright license would be directly incorporated into the
proprietary right vesting in a digital product, and would therefore become enforceable against everyone. For
more details on the characteristics of erga omnes rights and obligations, as opposed to other types of rights
and obligations, see: SARTOR, G. (2006) Fundamental Legal Concepts: A Formal and Teleological
Characterisation. Law Working Paper. European University Institute.
51
52
From a legal point of view, a right can be either in personam or in rem. A right in rem is a proprietary
right, which relates to the ownership of a thing and does not rely upon any contractual relationship, as a right
in personam necessarily does. Likewise, an obligation in rem, as opposed to an obligation in personam, is
an obligation which relates to the proprietary right in a thing. Accordingly, since they are not concerned with
any personal or contractual relationship, rights and obligations in rem are inherent to the thing into which
they have been embodied, irrespectively of the owner thereof. The right can thus be enforced against
anyone who comes into possession of the thing and will be passed to any subsequent owner along with the
ownership of the thing. For a more detailed overview of the distinction between rights in personam and rights
in rem, see MERRILL, T. W. & SMITH, H. E. (2001) The Property/Contract Interface. Columbia Law Review,
101.
53
Copyright law has been designed to counterbalance the deadweight loss deriving from the initial
appropriation of information with the long-term benefits deriving from the widespread dissemination and free
availability of information. The exclusive rights granted by the copyright regime are therefore weaker than a
95
6. Mandatory Requirement of Notice
In order to reduce the costs of processing information, the regime of
property law in many jurisdictions endorsed the idea that proprietary rights in a
thing must necessarily comprise a default set of rights which may not be
disposed of separately,54 although they may nevertheless be licensed to third
parties by contractual means. For instance, the numerus clausus principle of
property rights, according to which only a limited number of exceptions are
allowed to deviate from the unitary principle of property law,55 has been widely
adopted in the property regime of most civil law jurisdictions and beyond.56
Under the actual copyright regime, the owner of any given instance of a
work is in fact granted with full ownership of the item, although the exercise of
that proprietary right is limited to the extent that it does not infringe upon
another right vesting in the same work, namely, the copyright in the original
work of authorship.57 The reduction in the costs of processing information with
regard to the nature of the property right vesting in the digital instance of a work
should therefore be counterbalanced with the increased costs to be incurred in
standard property right to the extent that they only allow for the limited appropriation of a work, as they are
themselves limited in duration and in scope. See e.g. LANDES, W. M. & POSNER, R. A. (1989) An
Economic Analysis of Copyright Law. The Journal of Legal Studies, 18. Accordingly, in order to preserve the
original ratio of the copyright regime, whenever the copyright in a work expires, any restrictions which have
been imposed upon the exploitation of a particular instance of the work should equally expire. As soon as
the term of the copyright in a work is over, all the restrictions impinging upon the exploitation of the
proprietary right vesting in the digital manifestation of the work should therefore automatically come to an
end and full ownership be granted to the owner of the digital work.
54
See PARISI, F. (2002) Entropy in Property. American Journal of Comparative Law, 50.
The numerus clausus (closed number) principle in property law is a principle according to which only a
limited set of property rights are made available in any given legal system, see RUDDEN, B. (1987)
Economic Theory v Property Law: The Numerus Clausus Problem. IN EEKELAAR, J. & BELL, J. (Eds.)
Oxford Essays on Jurisprudence.
55
56
Originating from the principles of Roman law, the numerus clausus principle has been adopted by a
large number of civil law jurisdictions, as an attempt to reduce the potential fragmentation of property rights.
Although not expressly articulated in the legal system of most common law countries, the principle may also
be found in some aspects of the common law tradition which are basically aimed at discouraging the
creation of new typologies of rights enforceable against the world at large. See MERRILL, T. & SMITH, H.
(2000) Optimal Standardization in the Law of Property: The Numerus Clausus Principle. Yale Law Journal,
110.
See e.g. GINSBURG, J. C. (1992) Conflicts of Copyright Ownership Between Authors and Owners of
Original Artworks: An Essay in Comparative and International Private Law. Columbia Journal of Law & the
Arts, 17. and, more in general, KINSELLA, N. S. (2001) Against Intellectual Property. Journal of Libertarian
Studies, 15.
57
96
order to identify the copyright status of the work and the various terms and
conditions under which it has been released.
If the numerous clausus principle is exclusively based on the need to
decrease transaction costs to ensure that all assets are put to their most valuable
use,58 however, a proper mechanism of notification allowing for the immediate
verification of the content of any given property right would not necessarily
infringe upon the principles of property law. In fact, to the extent that the
restrictions and/or obligations restraining the scope of the property rights
vesting in the digital manifestation of a work can be precisely defined and
communicated to the public, and insofar as the ownership of the digital work,
albeit limited, only pertains to one individual right holder, the establishment of
a new typology of property rights is unlikely to impose any restriction upon the
free circulation of goods or to negatively affect the most efficient allocation of
resources to the parties who will put them into the most efficient uses.59
Accordingly, the law may limit the number of property rights by merely
regulating the level of notice that is required in order to establish a new
typology of property rights. A number of verification rules have in fact been
implemented in order to justify the emergence of atypical proprietary claims
over particular assets.60 Any given verification rule involves however a series of
costs both for right holders to establish the proper scope of their rights in an
asset and for users to ascertain the legal status of the asset, as well as for the
implementation of the property system as a whole.61 A new typology of
Originally meant to encourage the free circulation of goods by limiting the number of different property
rights that may vest in any given resource, the numerus clausus principle has also been justified in terms of
economic efficiency through the theory of the anti-commons. See MICHELMAN, F. (1982) Ethics,
Economics and the Law of Property. Nomos, 24. and HELLER, M. A. (1998) The Tragedy of the
Anticommons: Property in the Transition from Marx to Markets. Harvard Law Review, 111.
58
See, in particular, HANSMANN, H. & KRAAKMAN, R. (2002) Property, Contract and Verification: The
Numerus Clausus Problem and the Divisibility of Rights. Harvard Law School. (claiming that the numerus
clausus principle is not specifically meant to restrict the number of property rights which can be created, but
is merely aimed at encouraging the use of a specific set of property rights which have been expressly
recognized by the legal system).
59
60
If the property right in a particular asset does not constitute full ownership of the asset, the party
interested in acquiring the right needs a mechanism to verify what is the proper scope of the right. For an
overview of the different types of verification rules, see HANSMANN, H. & KRAAKMAN, R. (2001) Property,
Contract, and Verifiability: Understanding the Law's Restrictions on Divided Rights. University of California,
Berkeley.
The more information is provided by a particular verification mechanism, the higher are the costs of
establishing and maintaining the verification system. Property rights related to different kinds of assets may
therefore have different verification rules which are designed to provide the maximum amount of information,
but only insofar as that the advantages deriving from the additional information are capable of justifying the
61
97
property rights will therefore be created only when the advantages deriving
from the emergence of the new right exceed the overall costs of creating and
administering the right.62
In particular, the principle of numerus clausus is mainly concerned with the
idea of limiting the categories of property rights which can be officially
recognized by the legal system rather than with the fact of restraining the
specific content of these rights.63 An alternative regime of property rights could
therefore emerge in the digital environment, allowing for the establishment of a
new form of property rights in the digital manifestation of a work, where the
actual scope of the right could be arbitrarily defined by the copyright owner to
the extent that the content of the right can be easily identified.64 In other words,
the proposed regime would essentially be based upon the concept of
ascertainability: whenever it becomes too difficult for the owner of a digital
work to ascertain the number and the scope of the proprietary rights vesting in a
particular instance of the work, the right would ultimately be regarded as a
standard property right and the protection granted to the work would thus
inevitably revert back to the default copyright protection regardless of the
various terms and conditions that had been originally incorpora